Wednesday, July 22, 2015
Corrective Justice, Reparations, and Race-Based Affirmative Action
I recently published a short essay (2500 words or so) regarding affirmative action with The Arkansas Journal of Social Change and Public Service, an online, student-run journal published at my law school. The article is available here. Comments are welcome, as always. Also, feel free to circulate as widely as you deem appropriate and in whatever ways are most convenient.
Friday, June 26, 2015
Brief Thoughts on Obergefell, the Same-Sex Marriage Case
I don’t
have time right now for a comprehensive analysis like with the Obamacare case. So here are some quick thoughts and I may follow up with more
details at a later time.
1. I agree with the
result. I think the Constitution does protect a right to same-sex
marriage. And I think the result in this case is the natural extension of
existing precedent. There were multiple analytical bases to get to this
result, all of which I find persuasive.
2. However, I think the
issue is a close call. Thus, a 5-4 result is both unsurprising and
justified. In my view, the majority is correct, but by a small
margin. The dissenters are on very firm ground in disagreeing with the
result, and even firmer ground in raising concerns about Kennedy’s interpretive methodology.
3. Kennedy has become quite
a master at the use of sweeping language. Much of what he wrote is
beautiful. But beauty needs to be backed up with analytical rigor.
And in the latter department, Kennedy’s opinions is lacking. Not like in Lawrence
v. Texas (the 2003 sodomy case), but it is still too all-over-the
place. In addition, Kennedy appears to have finalized his rejection of
the long-established framework for addressing due process and equal protection
issues (at least in “family privacy” cases). I wish he had been more
explicit about the fact that he was doing so.
4. Roberts’s dissent is very
solid. He is a terrific writer. And much of his analysis is
excellent (though he does overstate the case in a number of places).
5. As I said above, I do
think the dissents make important points about the dangers of Kennedy’s
sweeping language and the interpretive methodology it suggests. However, I
ultimately think their worries for democracy are somewhat misplaced. The
Court will never go as far as they fear, even with Kennedy’s broad rhetoric
available as a tool. Moreover, the result today is not as extreme as Roe,
which remains at the outer boundary of “substantive due process”—the source of
the constitutional right to privacy/liberty/autonomy. But the dissenters’
concerns are certainly understandable. An honest reading of Kennedy’s
opinion could easily justify some pretty dramatic results. Nonetheless, the
better reading is a more circumscribed view of constitutional liberty. In
other words, Kennedy’s sweeping language must be read in the context of the
history of “family privacy” cases—marriage, contraception, abortion, initiate
relations. Limiting his language to that domain, today’s case does not
create quite the danger that the dissenters contend. Again, though, there
are legitimate bases to stretch the case beyond family privacy, and then the
dissenters fears could, in theory, be realized.
6. Some news reports have
questioned how Roberts can be “on both sides” in these two cases--the Obamacare case and this one. But
there is nothing contradictory about what Roberts did. In
each case, he took the side of judicial restraint based on extremely plausible
interpretive arguments. Roberts may be wrong in one, both, or neither of the cases. But his approach was
deeply principled.
7. I think this is a very
good day for constitutional liberty generally and a truly great day for GLBT
rights specifically.
Analysis of King v. Burwell -- The Obamacare Tax Subsidies Case
Here are my thoughts on the
Supreme Court’s decision on June 25, 2015, in King v. Burwell. In that
case, the Court ruled that tax subsides are available to those purchasing
health insurance on both (1) exchanges set up by a state itself, and (2)
exchanges set up by the federal government for a state. I agree with the
Court’s ruling. While I believe reasonable minds can differ in this
case—something that is virtually always true when the decision is 6 to 3—I
think the majority has the better argument, and by a good margin.
It will be difficult for me to
write a summary of the case that digs deeply into the substance without almost
rewriting the various opinions in full. That is because complex statutory
interpretation cases, like complex contract interpretation issues, come down to
the weight of the evidence taken as a whole. There are numerous relevant
categories of evidence in these types of lawsuits. And there are often multiple pieces of
evidence from each category. That is certainly true in King v.
Burwell. As a result, any true summary that I could write would leave out
critical detail. Given that, and for reasons of time, I am going to
summarize the opinions in more general terms and include selected arguments for
each side.
Before getting to those thoughts,
however, let me note that statutory interpretation is not rocket science.
And it does not take a law degree to understand the basic concepts, even if it
does take such a degree to capture some of the deeper nuances.
Accordingly, given that the case is not that long, those nonlawyers (and
lawyers) deeply interested in this matter ought to consider reading the case in
full rather than relying solely upon my assessment below. The opinion is available here on the Supreme Court’s website.
Now, to business. The Affordable Care Act says that tax
subsidies are available to those people who buy health insurance on an exchange
“established by the State.” Given that the statute defines “State” to
mean the 50 states and some territories, there is a good case that the four-word
phrase “Established by the state” means that a person may only receive tax
subsidies if the person buys insurance on a state exchange; those purchasing on
a federal exchange may not receive the subsidies. However, the single
most important principle in statutory, contractual, and constitutional
interpretation is that language must be read in context. And the full
context of the statute creates a powerful argument that “established by the
State,” as used in the relevant provision, does not rule out subsidies on
federal exchanges. Indeed, Chief Justice Roberts marshals multiple types
of arguments to make a compelling case that the tax subsidies apply to both
state and federal exchanges, including (1) textual arguments (a close
reading of the text), (2) structural arguments (analyzing the
relationship of textual provisions throughout the statute), (3) purposive
arguments (assessing the purposes or goals of the act, as reflected in both the
language of the statute and material from outside the statute—called “extrinsic
evidence”—such as legislative history), and (4) consequential arguments
(focusing on the consequences of various interpretations and how those
consequences match up with the language and purposes of the statute).
For an example of a close textual
reading, the statute provides that if the state chooses not to set up an
exchange, the federal government “shall . . . establish and operate such
Exchange within the state.”
(Emphasis added.) Roberts argues
that this means that federal exchanges essentially stand in for state exchanges
and should be treated in the same manner for many purposes. In other words, Roberts is saying that the
words “such exchange” support the conclusion that any federal exchange just
is a state exchange (for many purposes).
For an example of a structural
reading, Roberts points out that if tax subsidies are only available on state
exchanges, then there will be no individuals who meet the tax
subsidy eligibility standards in states with a federal exchange. But,
Roberts continues, the statute “clearly contemplates” that there will be
qualified individuals for every exchange because all
exchanges must make available health plans for qualified individuals. How
can an exchange make available health plans for qualified individuals if there are
no qualified individuals for that exchange? To put this argument
in broad terms, Roberts is arguing that between the two readings of
“established by the State,” one creates a conflict with other language in the
statute and one doesn’t. Consistent with long-established canons of
statutory (and contractual) interpretation, it is better to chose the reading
that avoids the conflict—the reading that allows subsidies for the federal
exchanges.
Here is an example of an argument
that combines structural, purposive, and consequentialist reasoning.
First, some basic principles. The guaranteed
issue provision requires that insurance companies provide insurance to
anyone who requests to buy it regardless of preexisting conditions. The community rating provision
requires that everyone be charged largely the same price for health insurance
regardless of their health condition.
And the individual mandate provision requires that everyone own
insurance or pay a tax/penalty. Roberts
argues that these provisions will not work together as intended by the
Affordable Care Act if the tax subsidies are not available on federal
exchanges. That is because, without the subsidies, many people cannot
afford to buy insurance on the exchanges. Most of those people will then
be exempt from the individual mandate under one of the exceptions in the law
and thus need not buy insurance. Next, if the healthy people in that
group do not buy insurance and the sick people do (a very likely occurrence),
that will raise premiums, pricing more healthy people out of the market. Finally, as more people are priced out of the
market, insurance will become even more expensive, creating a feedback loop
that Roberts calls a “death spiral.”
That feedback loop will defeat essential purposes of Obamacare reflected
throughout the statute.
Roberts makes other powerful
arguments. In fact, I agreed with almost every point he made. I do
believe he overstated his case in a couple of places. But overall, his
arguments—and responses to the dissent’s arguments—were excellent.
Turning to the dissent, Justice
Scalia presented a number of solid points. But unlike Roberts, he also
makes a number of unpersuasive arguments; and he overstates in multiple places.
Scalia makes more than a dozen distinct
arguments in the dissent. But I think
three stand out from the others as strong bases for his position.
First, Scalia contends that the
words “exchange established by the State” will have no meaning in the provision in
question if that provision applies to both federal and state exchanges.
Such a result violates the canon of interpretation that all words in a legal
text should be given meaning, if possible. But I called this a “canon”
for a reason. It is not a rule. It is just one, albeit important, factor
to consider when interpreting legal language. Moreover, the canon may not
even apply here. Remember that Roberts essentially argues that
“established by the State” incorporates the federal exchanges
due to other language (e.g., “such exchange” discussed above). That would
mean the three highlighted words do have meaning—just not their
ordinary meaning.
Second, Congress chose to use the
word “exchange” in some places and the phrase “exchange established by
the State” in others. That suggests that “exchange” and “exchange
established
by the State” have different meanings.
Point for Scalia. This is one of Scalia’s strongest arguments, if
not the best.
Third, Congress wrote that if a
territory establishes an exchange (e.g., Puerto Rico, Guam, or the U.S. Virgin
Islands), it shall be treated the same as if a state established the
exchange. Why didn’t Congress do the same with respect to exchanges
established by the Federal Government? Another good argument for
Scalia. However, Roberts essentially argues, in response, that Congress
did not need to craft a similar provision for federal exchanges because the
phrase “such Exchange,” discussed above, obviated the need to do so.
These three points, when mixed
with a couple of other decent arguments Scalia offers, are simply not
sufficient to overcome the much larger collection of persuasive arguments that
Roberts presents.
As I said, Scalia also makes some
unpersuasive arguments throughout his dissent. Here are three
examples.
First, Scalia writes that it would
be “hard to come up with a clearer way to limit tax credits to state Exchanges
than to use the words ‘established by the State.’” This is false. In fact, it is actually quite easy to come up
with stronger language. Scalia fails to
see this because he ignores a basic and recognized principle in both statutory
and contract drafting: If your goal is to exclude something, it is always more
effective to exclude that thing expressly than it is to implicitly
exclude it by simply leaving that thing out of a list of what is included. And failing to follow this rule has cost
legislatures and contracting parties in more cases than I can count.
Given this principle, here are three examples of how the language could more
clearly have prohibited subsidies on the federal exchanges:
1. “. . . exchanges established by the State, excluding those
created by the Secretary of Health and Human Services,”
2. “. . . exchanges established by the State pursuant to [the
section setting forth the precise manner in which state exchanges are created]
and not pursuant to [the section setting forth the precise manner in which
federal exchanges are created]
3. “. . . exchanges, except those established by the Secretary
of Health and Human Services.”
All of these are clearly superior
to the current wording in the statute, if the goal is to establish that tax
subsidies do not apply to federal exchanges.
Second, Scalia essentially argues
that “established by the State” must have the same meaning in each provision in
which it is used in the act. And if the four words are ignored when it
comes to tax subsidies, the same must be true elsewhere. This is incorrect.
It is indisputable that the same language can, and often does, mean different
things in different contexts, even within the same statute or contract.
The fact that the same phrase is used in two places in a law or contract is
important evidence that the meaning is the same. But it is not the
stringent rule that Scalia suggests.
Moreover, Roberts is best read as not actually arguing that the words
mean something different in the relevant provision. Instead, he is arguing that the provision,
when read in context, does not exclude tax subsidies from federal exchanges because
federal exchanges are supposed to be treated the same as state exchanges (at
least for this purpose).
Third, according to the majority,
if the tax subsidies are not available, then certain other provisions in the
law would make little sense. Scalia responds by saying that this only
shows “oddity, not ambiguity.” But here Scalia misses the point.
Oddity is precisely one of the bases that counts in favor of rejecting an
interpretation. Scalia is correct that oddity and ambiguity are two
different things. But the odder the result of an interpretation, the
weaker that interpretation is. Scalia continues by saying that laws often
have unusual or mismatched provisions. But when an interpretation leads
to an usual result or a mismatch of two sections of a statute, that counts
against the interpretation. This result
flows from multiple canons of construction, including (1) the preference for
reasonable interpretations, (2) the preference for interpretations that are
consistent with the principal purpose of a law, and (3) the canon that
provisions should be read in harmony if possible.
Let me end by noting that King v.
Burwell is a rather run-of-the mill case on statutory interpretation. The opinions reflected some of the basic
divisions among the members of the Court (and among lawyers and law professors
more generally) regarding the appropriate method for interpreting statutes (and
contracts and constitutions). But both Roberts’s majority opinions and
Scalia’s dissent were perfectly normal Supreme Court opinions addressing a
perfectly mundane case (from the perspective of statutory
interpretation). Yes, this case had high political salience. Thus, the
attention it will get and the rhetoric it will spawn is going to be
abnormal. Indeed, Scalia’s dissent is
filled with sky-is-falling rhetoric. But that is rather common in
dissents in cases like this—cases with high political salience. Had
Roberts and Kennedy sided with the Conservatives, I am rather sure that one of
the four Liberals would have used similar rhetoric in dissent, much like
Ginsburg (wrongfully) did in the Hobby Lobby/religious accommodation
case. In short, do not believe any
statements that this case has “fundamentally altered our constitutional order”
or any other such hyperbolic nonsense. This was a typical statutory
construction case, quite similar to the statutory and contract interpretation
disputes American courts handle every day.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)